Relativity of
Simultaneity
When Einstein first hit upon special relativity, he thought
one effect of special importance, so much so that it fills the first section of
his "On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies." It is the relativity of
simultaneity. According to it, inertial observers in
relative motion disagree on the timing of events at different places. If
one observer thinks that two events are simultaneous, another might not. At
first this will seem like just another of the many novel effects relativity
brings. However, as we explore more deeply, you will see that this is the
central adjustment Einstein made to our understanding of space and time in
special relativity . Once you grasp it, everything else makes sense. (And until
you do, nothing quite makes sense!)
Using Light Signals to Judge the Time Order of Events
There is a quick way to see how this comes about. Imagine a
long platform with an observer located at its midpoint. At either end, at the
places marked A and B, there are two momentary flashes of light. The light
propagates from these events to the observer. Let us imagine that they arrive
at the same moment, as they do in the animation below. Noticing that they
arrive at the same moment and that they come from places equal distances away,
the observer will decide that the two events happened
simultaneous.
Another outcome is closely related. Imagine also that there
are clocks located at A and B. If both clocks show the same reading at the
events of the two flashes, then we would judge the two clocks to be properly synchronized. That is what the
platform observer judges since, as the animation shows, both clocks read "0"
when the flashes occur at each location.
Here's a version that isn't animated.
So far, nothing remarkable has happened. That is about to change.
Now consider this process from the point of view of an observer who moves relative to the platform along its length. For that new observer, the platform moves rapidly and, in the animation, in the direction from A towards B. Once again there will be two flashes and light from them will propagate towards the observer at the midpoint of the platform. However the midpoint is in motion. It is rushing away from light coming from A; and rushing toward the light coming from B. Nonetheless, the two signals arrive at the midpoint at the same moment.
Here's a version that isn't animated.
What is the new observer to make of this? For the new observer, the light from A must cover a greater distance to catch up with the receding midpoint; and the light from B must cover a lesser distance to arrive at the midpoint rushing towards it. So if the two arrive at the same moment, the light from A must have left earlier than the light from B to give it greater time to cover the greater distance to get to the midpoint. That is, the flash at A happened earlier than the flash at B. The two events were not simultaneous, according to the new observer. | Notice that the reasoning requires the light postulate: both light flashes must move at the same speed; that is, each must require the same time to cover the same distance. |
The reasoning extends to the clocks. The clocks at A and B
show the same time "0" when the flash events happen at each. These two events are
not simultaneous for the new observer. Therefore the new observer will judge
the clocks at A and B not to be properly synchronized.
In fact clock A is set ahead of, that is, earlier than clock B, for it reads "0" earlier than clock B.
Relativity of Simultaneity without Light Signals
The effect just described is the relativity of
simultaneity. The account above uses light signals merely as a means to
enable the two observers to determine the time order of the events. The light signals themselves are not an essential part of the effect and they can be distracting. We can describe the effect without them as follows.
On the platform, we have two events.
The A-event at the A-end of the platform coincides with the setting of the A clock to 0.
The B-event at the B-end of the platform coincides with the setting of the B clock to 0.
So far we have said nothing about the order in time of these two events.
The B-event at the B-end of the platform coincides with the setting of the B clock to 0.
So far we have said nothing about the order in time of these two events.
Two observers in relative motion disagree on the timing of the two events and on the associated synchrony of the clocks.
We shall take the case in which a platform observer judges the A- and B-events to be simultaneous and the A-clock and B-clock to be properly synchronized.
Then an observer moving relative to the platform and with motion parallel to it judges that:
-- the trailing A-event at the rear of moving platform occurs earlier; and the A-clock is set earlier than the B-clock.
-- the leading B-event at the front of the moving platform occurs later; and the B-clock is set later than the A-clock
-- the trailing A-event at the rear of moving platform occurs earlier; and the A-clock is set earlier than the B-clock.
-- the leading B-event at the front of the moving platform occurs later; and the B-clock is set later than the A-clock
.
The simple rule to help you keep track of which event happens when in this particular situation is this:
trailing event -- earlier
leading event -- later.
trailing event -- earlier
leading event -- later.
Who is Right?
The two observers disagree on the timing of the events
and the synchrony of the clocks. It is easy to imagine that one of them
has made a mistake and the other is right. That would be comfortable
for it would require no adjustments to our concept of time. However, NEITHER has made a mistake or has been somehow misinformed. Rather it is that judgements of the simultaneity of spatially
separated events depend on the motion of the observer, just as the rates of clocks and lengths
of bodies depend on the motion of the observer in special relativity.
There is no absolute fact
as to whether two spatially separated events are simultaneous. There is
only a fact of simultaneity or its failure relative to an inertial
frame of reference.
That a moving clock slows and moving rod shrinks is something
most of us get used to with a little thought. The same is not true of the
relativity of simultaneity. It is harder to get used to it, since it amounts to
a more fundamental breakdown. It tells us that that there is no absolute fact
about the relative timing of events at distant places. Imagine that you have
candles on a birthday cake in Pittsburgh and on one
in far-away Sydney. You plan to have them blown out at exactly the same
moment. The relativity of simultaneity tells you that there is no absolute fact
to whether you succeed. Relative to an earth-bound observer, you may succeed.
But that can mean that relative to an observer on the moon, who moves relative
to the earth, you did not succeed.
The relativity of simultaneity adds to
the repertoire of quantities that are relative and not absolute. There
is no absolute fact to whether a spaceship is moving uniformly or is at rest.
It can only be said to be at rest relative to another body. There is no
absolute fact as to whether a rod is a foot long or a process lasts for one
minute. They can only true with respect an observer with a definite state of
motion. To this list we add that there is no absolute fact to whether two
spatially separated events are simultaneous; or whether two spatially separated
clocks are synchronous. These can only be true relative to an observer with a
definite state of motion.
What the Relativity of Simultaneity is NOT
There is a quite benign way in which observers can disagree
on the simultaneity of events. It is not the effect at issue. To see the benign
way, imagine that a flash of lightning strikes the tree you are standing under.
Let us say the strike comprises two events: the flash of
the light and the boom of the thunder. For you standing under the tree,
if you survive, the two events are simultaneous. It would not appear so for
someone standing on a distant hill top watching the lightning strike. That
observer would see the flash and then, several seconds later, hear the boom of
the thunder. For you the flash and the boom are simultaneous. For the distant
observer they are not simultanteous; or, more precisely, they do not
appear simultaneous.
This same effect can arise in more abstruse settings. When we
look at a distant galaxy 10 million light years away, we are seeing it as it appeared 10 million years ago. So if we see some
event occuring now, such as a star in the galaxy exploding, that event really
happened 10 millions years ago. It will appear to us that it happened
now, at the same time as the events of the present day. In fact it did not. We
know that and we correct for the time the starlight took to reach us in judging
the timing of the event.
http://www.nasa.gov/multimedia/imagegallery/image_feature_1748.html
These two examples illustrate the oddities of what we can
call "appearance simultaneity." Events are
simultaneous in this sense, merely if our sensations of them happen at the same
moment. Or they fail to be simultaneous in this sense if our sensations of them
happen at different times.
That sort of simultaneity is not the sort that is at issue in
the relativity of simultaneity. The idea is that we correct for differences in appearance simultaneity. For
example, when we hear the boom of the thunder coming after we see the flash of
the lightning, we routinely allow for the fact that light travels very rapidly,
but sound travels slowly--roughly one mile in five seconds. So even though we
sense the flash and boom at different times, we judge the two originating
events to be simultaneous.
Here's another case. Two lightning bolts strike at points D
and E, where D is farther away from the observer. Let's say that the strikes
are timed so that light signals from the bolts arrive at the same moment at the
observer. The observer would see both flashes at the same time. The bolts would
appear simultaneous. But the observer would then correct
for the greater distance that the light signal from D must travel. So
that the observer sees the flashes at the same time means the observer judges
the D bolt to have struck earlier.
The relativity of simultaneity of relativity theory arises
after we have corrected for the oddities of appearance simultaneity. Even after
those corrections have been made, it turns out that observers in relative
motion will not agree on the timing of spatially separated events. In the
thought experiment above with the A and B clocks, it turns out that no
corrections for appearance simultaneity are needed. Since the observer is
located at the midpoint of the platform, the
flashes of light at A and B are delayed equally. That is why the observer was
placed there.
No comments:
Post a Comment